Chapter Info (Click Here)
Book No. – 20 (Philosophy)
Book Name – Contemporary Theories of Knowledge – John L. Pollock
What’s Inside the Chapter? (After Subscription)
1. Epistemological Theories
2. Human Rationality
3. Epistemological Methodology
4. Naturalized Epistemology
4.1. Ontological Naturalism
4.2. Methodological Naturalism
4.3. Naturalism and Psychology
4.4. Naturalistic Internalism
5. Generic Rationality
6. Truth and the Evaluation of Cognitive Architectures
7. How to Build a Person
7.1. Oscar I
7.2. Oscar II
7.3. Oscar III
7.4. Mental Representations
8. Conclusions
Note: The first chapter of every book is free.
Access this chapter with any subscription below:
- Half Yearly Plan (All Subject)
- Annual Plan (All Subject)
- Philosophy (Single Subject)
- CUET PG + Philosophy
- UGC NET + Philosophy
Epistemology and Rationality
Chapter – 6

Epistemological Theories
Epistemology studies rational cognition and how we can know various claims.
Investigations occur on several levels:
Lowest level: Theories of particular kinds of knowledge (perceptual knowledge, induction, knowledge of other minds, mathematical knowledge, etc.).
Intermediate level: Topics that apply to most specific kinds of knowledge, such as theories of reasoning (deductive and defeasible).
Highest level: General epistemological theories explaining how justified belief in general is possible. Examples include foundationalism, coherentism, probabilism, reliabilism, and direct realism.
Highest level theories can be seen in two ways:
Structural theories of epistemic justification: Describe overall structural relations that produce epistemic justification, explaining how cognition constituents fit together.
Analytic theories of epistemic justification: Logical analyses explaining why epistemic justification has its general structure.
The distinction between structural and analytic theories is often vague; analytic theories explain what would make structural theories true.
Foundationalism, coherentism, and direct realism are usually structural theories, while reliabilism is often seen as an analytic theory.
Reliabilism can support a foundationalist structural theory by justifying it as a reliable way of acquiring knowledge, showing these theories are not necessarily incompatible.
Foundationalists, coherentists, and direct realists often claim their theories are also analytic, meaning their structural accounts are constitutive of the concept of epistemic justification.
These analytic theories explain justification by enumerating principles that give rise to it rather than an overarching principle like reliabilism.
A main objection to foundationalist, coherentist, and direct realist analytic theories is that they provide piecemeal, ad hoc analyses, characterizing epistemic justification with a general structure plus many unrelated principles without a unifying account.
This leads to inelegance and leaves open whether there is a deeper explanation unifying these principles.
Probabilism and reliabilism aim to provide general, elegant accounts avoiding ad hoc problems, but neither fully succeeds.
No familiar structural theory of epistemic justification gives a truly unified account, leaving the theoretical situation unsatisfactory.
The question remains: What is the origin of the complex epistemic structure that yields justified beliefs?
Insight may come from a careful study of the concept of epistemic justification itself.
Distinction is important between procedural epistemic justification and a justification concept tied to knowledge and the Gettier problem.
The focus here is on procedural epistemic justification, which will necessarily include a complex structure with many apparently unrelated epistemic principles.
The key question is: What unifies these diverse principles as part of the true theory of epistemic justification?
This question should be placed in a broader context: epistemic cognition is part of rational cognition in general.
There is a traditional distinction between epistemic cognition (about what to believe) and practical cognition (about what to do).
Rational agents are those who cognize rationally; correct epistemic cognition is a subspecies of rational cognition overall.
Asking what makes epistemic procedures correct is a special case of what makes cognitive procedures rational.
Procedural epistemology is therefore part of a general theory of rationality, which also must account for how goals are selected and how actions are chosen.
Human Rationality
The question: “What makes rational procedures rational?” can be illuminated by examining philosophical methods for answering how to perform cognitive tasks rationally (e.g., inductive reasoning).
Philosophers propose general principles (like the Nicod principle, Bayesian inference, hypothetico-deductive method) and test them on concrete examples.
Testing requires knowing how the example should turn out; e.g., Nelson Goodman’s grue/bleen example demonstrated the need for a projectibility constraint in induction.
Everyone agrees that inductive reasoning violating projectibility is irrational, but the standard answer for knowing this is “philosophical intuition,” which is vague.
Compare this to linguists studying grammaticality, who construct theories tested by grammaticality judgments from proficient speakers.
Similarly, humans can make rationality judgments about whether cognitive acts are rational or irrational; these judgments provide data to test theories of rationality.
Some philosophers argue rationality is about concepts and logic, making intuitions a kind of Platonic intuition; but this view is not applied to linguistic intuitions, which depend on linguistic convention.
Learning a language involves acquiring procedural knowledge—knowing how to do something—and there can be multiple procedural knowledges for a task.
Once procedural knowledge is acquired, one can reliably judge conformity to it, detecting divergences before failure (e.g., knowing when one is about to fall off a bicycle).
Competent speakers often produce ungrammatical utterances but can recognize and correct them on reflection.
Similarly, cognition involves procedural knowledge for how to cognize, which includes the ability to recognize when one diverges from it.
This ability to detect divergence is what “philosophical intuition” about rationality effectively amounts to.
Performance theories describe how people behave; competence theories describe people’s procedural knowledge for performing tasks.
People often fail to conform to their own procedural knowledge, so competence and performance can diverge greatly.
Philosophers’ theories of rationality based on intuitions are best seen as competence theories articulating the rules of our procedural knowledge for cognition.
In epistemic cognition, these rules correspond to our epistemic norms.
We have no direct access to these rules but can detect divergences from them and use this to confirm general principles about procedural knowledge.
Unlike linguistic knowledge, much of our procedural knowledge for cognition is innate, likely built in by evolution to avoid extreme epistemic vulnerability.
Empirical evidence shows universal patterns in reasoning, such as modus ponens being natural and modus tollens initially unnatural but later learned.
The rules of our procedural cognitive knowledge are not mere generalizations about behavior (performance) but rules we try to conform to; detecting divergence leads to correction of our cognition.
Human rationality consists of principles built into our cognitive architecture.
In epistemology, the diverse principles of a correct structural theory of epistemic justification are unified by being built into human cognition—there need not be a more general characterization explaining why these principles hold.
The proposal: a theory of human rationality is a competence theory of human cognition, eliciting procedural norms governing cognitive performance.
When such norms govern epistemic cognition, they are called epistemic norms.
Procedural epistemic justification consists in holding beliefs in compliance with correct epistemic norms.
Proposed analysis of epistemic justification:
A belief is justified if and only if it is held in compliance with the cognizer’s epistemic norms.Distinction between acting in accordance with norms and acting in compliance with norms is crucial.
Acting in accordance means behavior does not violate the norm, but might not be guided by the norm.
Acting in compliance means behavior follows and is guided by the norm.
Justification requires compliance, not merely accordance.
This is a naturalistic analysis of epistemic justification.
Cognition consists of natural processes governed by internalized norms.
Epistemic norms are defined as norms that actually govern our cognition.
No informative logical analysis of the governance process is expected or possible; it is a natural process observed empirically.
The nature of governance can be clarified by psychological investigation only.
This is similar to how we understand natural kinds like electrons or magnetism—through empirical investigation, not logical analysis.
Objection: existing epistemological theories offer piecemeal and uninformative analyses of epistemic justification.
The proposed analysis escapes this objection by providing a completely general and unified account of epistemic justification as compliance with procedural norms.
Structural theories arising from this analytic theory will be piecemeal due to the specificity of procedural norms.
Procedural norms are specific, responding only to directly accessible features of the current cognitive situation.
Norms cannot appeal to broad general features like “reliability of the process.”
Example: bicycle riding norms are very specific and situational (e.g., “If losing momentum, push harder”).
Epistemic norms are similarly specific, e.g., “If something looks red and you have no reason to doubt it, you may believe it is red.”
No single simple formula can combine all epistemic norms, just like no simple formula governs all bicycle controls.
Contrast with conventional internalist epistemology: internalists claim epistemic norms describe how we actually reason.
This internalist claim is misleading because we do not always reason correctly.
Correct reasoning is precisely conforming to the epistemic norms, not merely how we happen to reason.
Analogy: bike-riding norms describe how we ride correctly, not all actual riding behavior.
Traditional accounts face a puzzle: norms describe correct action, but actual behavior can deviate.
Puzzle resolved by understanding norms as those that actually guide correct behavior (bike riding or reasoning).
Norms should be elicited from actual behavior, not from some separate external criterion.
Important difference: this formulation does not take actual reasoning behavior at face value, but recognizes the role of norms in guiding correct behavior.