Chapter Info (Click Here)
Book Name – An Introduction to Ethics (William Lillie)
What’s Inside the Chapter? (After Subscription)
1. The Concept of Evolution
2. The Theory of Herbert Spencer
3. Evolution without ‘Teleology
4. Natural Selection in Ethics
5. Modern Theories of Evolution
6. Creative Morality
Note: The first chapter of every book is free.
Access this chapter with any subscription below:
- Half Yearly Plan (All Subject)
- Annual Plan (All Subject)
- Sociology (Single Subject)
- CUET PG + Philosophy
- UGC NET + Philosophy
The Standard as Determined by Revolution
Chapter – 10

The Concept of Evolution
The word evolution can refer generally to any development or specifically to biological development as taught by Charles Darwin in Origin of Species (1859).
The notion of development was familiar to philosophers and biologists from Aristotle, evident in the growth of an individual animal or plant from embryo or seed to fully grown form.
Before Darwin, thinkers considered that similar development occurred in the history of species or even the universe.
Darwin’s theory denied that animals and plants were due to special creative acts of God, instead proposing they developed from earlier, dissimilar kinds.
The laws of development in Darwinian theory are natural selection and the survival of the fittest.
Example: In snowy regions, rabbits with lighter coloration survive better due to camouflage, while darker rabbits are preyed upon. Over time, lighter rabbits become more numerous.
Natural selection explains the disappearance of monsters found only as fossils and the replacement by familiar animals.
Historical examples include brown rats replacing black rats in 18th-century Great Britain.
Even in biology, natural selection is only one of many tendencies influencing development.
Darwinian evolution was soon applied figuratively to societies, institutions, religion, art, morals, and conduct.
Evolutionary application sometimes implies changes follow natural selection and survival of the fittest.
In studying human conduct, there is recognition of development in behavior and standards of judgment, with surviving conduct often more fitted to circumstances.
Purely evolutionary ethics would define better conduct as simply more developed conduct later in history, which few moralists accept.
Evolutionists may note that later conduct is factually better than earlier conduct, but do not define good in terms of development.
Defining ethical terms via historical or biological development risks Moore’s naturalistic fallacy; “good” in common speech does not mean later in evolution.
Darwinian theory links good conduct with survival, suggesting conduct that survives in a struggle for existence is better.
Some evolutionists claim conduct that ensures individual or racial survival is good, but this is teleological, not evolutionary, as it sets prolongation of life as the ultimate end.
Most so-called evolutionary ethics introduce a standard beyond evolution, showing instability in purely evolutionary theories.
This instability is evident in Herbert Spencer’s evolutionary ethics, a major 19th-century example.