Book No. –  20 (Philosophy)

Book Name Contemporary Theories of  Knowledge – John L. Pollock

What’s Inside the Chapter? (After Subscription)

1. Motivation

2. A Taxonomy of Coherence Theories

2.1. Positive and Negative Coherence Theories

2.2. Linear and Holistic Coherence Theories

2.3. The Regress Argument

2.4. The Isolation Argument

3. Holistic Positive Coherence Theories

3.1. Lehrer’s Theory

3.2. Problems for Holistic Positive Coherence Theories

4. Negative Coherence Theories

4.1. Harman’s Theory

4.2. Problems with Negative Coherence Theories

5. Nondoxastic Theories and Direct Realism

Note: The first chapter of every book is free.

Access this chapter with any subscription below:

  • Half Yearly Plan (All Subject)
  • Annual Plan (All Subject)
  • Philosophy (Single Subject)
  • CUET PG + Philosophy
  • UGC NET + Philosophy
LANGUAGE

Coherence Theories of Knowledge

Chapter – 3

Picture of Harshit Sharma
Harshit Sharma

Alumnus (BHU)

Follow
Table of Contents

Motivation

  • Doxastic theories assume that only what other beliefs one holds determines whether a belief is justifiable.

  • Foundations theories grant a privileged role to a subclass of beliefs—the epistemologically basic beliefs—in this determination.

  • It has been argued there is no way to defend epistemologically basic beliefs.

  • The first alternative is to retain the doxastic assumption but reject basic beliefs, leading to a coherence theory.

  • A coherence theory denies the existence of a privileged subclass of beliefs; all beliefs have the same fundamental epistemic status.

  • Justifiability of a belief is determined by how it coheres with the entire set of one’s beliefs.

  • Different coherence theories vary by their account of the coherence relation, but all agree that justification depends on a belief’s relation to all beliefs, not a privileged subset.

  • One motivation for coherence theories is that since foundations theories are false, something like coherence theory must be true, given the doxastic assumption.

  • A second motivation is the Neurath metaphor: we are like sailors rebuilding a ship at sea, using our existing doxastic system of beliefs, including beliefs about how to modify beliefs.

  • We cannot abandon all beliefs to start fresh; procedural beliefs guide belief revision but are themselves revisable if they conflict too much with other beliefs.

  • The validity of an argument only requires we not accept premises and deny conclusion simultaneously; what to reject depends on our relative confidence.

  • Sometimes we might reject the validity of the argument itself, revising our beliefs about what counts as valid inference.

  • The general strategy is to make the entire belief set internally consistent, using procedural beliefs to guide its revision, while allowing revision of procedural beliefs themselves.

  • Although the Neurath metaphor motivates coherence theories, the philosophical credentials of coherence theories should be considered independently from it.

  • Part of the Neurath picture is mistaken: the assumption that belief change is always guided by beliefs is false.

  • For example, we reason by rules like modus ponens without necessarily having beliefs about these rules.

  • Many people, including non-philosophers, have few or no beliefs about the logical rules they follow in reasoning.

  • Complex reasoning, such as induction, often proceeds by rules that even philosophers cannot fully articulate.

  • We do not guide inductive reasoning by beliefs about the rules of induction.

  • Therefore, belief change is not always governed by beliefs about how to reason; many native reasoning processes operate via unarticulated rules without explicit beliefs about those rules.

  • It might be inessential to the Neurath picture that we hold beliefs about how to change beliefs.

  • A coherence theory could be defended by claiming belief change proceeds by reasoning from existing beliefs, weighing conflicts by relative confidence.

  • However, this is an incomplete account: belief change also involves acquisition of new beliefs via perception, which is not inference from other beliefs.

  • Perceptual beliefs enter the doxastic system without mediation by beliefs about how to acquire them.

  • Both perception and inference often occur “under the surface,” unmediated by procedural beliefs.

  • A correct account of belief change cannot rely exclusively on existing beliefs; it must also incorporate new perceptual beliefs.

  • The accommodation of perception is a major problem for any doxastic theory.

  • The doxastic assumption holds that justifiability of a belief depends exclusively on what one believes.

  • Foundations theories try to accommodate this by supposing perception results in beliefs about sensory experience which are self-justifying, allowing reasoning from these basic beliefs to perceptual knowledge.

  • The difficulty is that perception usually does not issue in beliefs about sensory experience, so perceptual knowledge cannot be based on reasoning from basic beliefs.

  • For coherence theories, it is unclear how perceptual beliefs enter the doxastic system under the doxastic assumption.

  • Although foundationalism is false, this does not clarify the true account of perceptual knowledge.

  • The core idea in the Neurath picture remains: beliefs are innocent until proven guilty.

  • We tend to become disengaged from the original reasons for our beliefs, remembering conclusions but not reasons.

  • Without memory of reasons, discrediting those reasons cannot discredit the belief itself.

  • This disengagement is a fact of human cognition due to limited information processing capacity; remembering reasons as well as conclusions would overwhelm memory.

  • This supports the idea of a web of interrelated beliefs, where justification depends on a belief’s secure niche in the network.

  • This networked structure aligns with what coherence theorists find appealing.

  • However, this structure is also compatible with foundations theories because of the role of memory.

  • In foundations theories, memory is analogous to sense perception; seeming to remember gives a defeasible reason to believe what is remembered.

  • When beliefs become disengaged from reasons and are stored in memory, recalling them involves believing them based on seeming to remember.

  • Such memory beliefs gain evidential status independent of original reasons, and are held unless defeated by stronger reasons.

  • When memory beliefs conflict, we weigh the strengths of mnemonic reasons, essentially measuring our confidence in those beliefs.

  • Thus, the correct part of the Neurath picture is accommodated by foundations theories, and does not argue in favor of coherence theories.

  • However, foundations theories fail because, in remembering, we rarely have beliefs about seeming to remember—i.e., we lack epistemologically basic beliefs.

  • The real disagreement between coherence and foundations theories lies in whether we have epistemologically basic beliefs.

  • Since we lack appropriate epistemologically basic beliefs, all foundations theories are false.

  • If the doxastic assumption holds, then some coherence theory must be true.

  • Alternatively, one can reject the doxastic assumption, thereby rejecting both foundations and coherence theories.

  • The downfall of foundations theories stems from their inability to handle perceptual input solely in terms of beliefs.

  • This suggests the real problem is the doxastic assumption, which will eventually be rejected.

  • Before rejecting the doxastic assumption, it is necessary to survey possible coherence theories to see if they can solve the problem.

Membership Required

You must be a member to access this content.

View Membership Levels

Already a member? Log in here

You cannot copy content of this page

error: Content is protected !!
Scroll to Top