Book No. –  19 (Philosophy)

Book Name The Fundamental Questions of Philosophy – A.C. Ewing

What’s Inside the Chapter? (After Subscription)

1. THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

2. THE FIRST CAUSE ARGUMENT

3. THE ARGUMENT FROM DESIGN

4. OTHER ARGUMENTS FOR GOD

5. MORAL ARGUMENTS. ETHICS AND RELIGION

6. THE ‘ARGUMENT FROM RELIGIOUS EXPERIENCE’

7. THE PROBLEM OF EVIL

Note: The first chapter of every book is free.

Access this chapter with any subscription below:

  • Half Yearly Plan (All Subject)
  • Annual Plan (All Subject)
  • Philosophy (Single Subject)
  • CUET PG + Philosophy
  • UGC NET + Philosophy
LANGUAGE

God (Philosophy)

Chapter – 11

Picture of Harshit Sharma
Harshit Sharma

Alumnus (BHU)

Follow
Table of Contents
  • The chapter addresses the philosophical question of greatest importance: the existence of God.

  • ‘God’ is understood here as a supreme mind, either omnipotent or at least more powerful than anything else, and supremely good and wise.

  • A purely philosophical work does not cover claims of revelation, which often underpin belief in God and His attributes.

  • Philosophers have developed a great number of arguments supporting the existence of God.

THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

  • The ontological argument attempts to prove God’s existence solely from the idea or definition of God.

  • God is defined as the most perfect being or one possessing all positive attributes.

  • The argument claims existence is a ‘perfection’ or positive attribute, so God must exist to avoid contradiction.

  • A major objection is that existence is not an attribute or perfection.

  • Saying something exists differs fundamentally from ascribing an ordinary attribute; existence affirms the concept is realized in fact, not that the concept gains a new characteristic.

  • Linguistic confusion arises because sentences like “cats exist” and “cats are carnivorous” share grammatical form but differ logically.

  • Saying “cats are carnivorous” adds a quality to already existing beings; saying “cats exist” asserts that propositions describing cats are true sometimes.

  • Negative case clarity: “dragons are non-existent” denies any entity has dragon-properties, without presupposing dragons exist, unlike “lions are not herbivorous” which presupposes lions exist.

  • Some say the ontological argument imperfectly expresses a principle: what we must think logically must be true of reality.

  • This principle is a necessary presupposition for all knowledge and justified belief.

  • Without this principle, no fact could be accepted and even experience would be unreliable.

  • However, this principle differs significantly from the traditional ontological argument and should not be conflated.

  • Moreover, to use this principle to prove God’s existence, one must already accept or justify that God exists, making the argument circular or self-evident.

THE FIRST CAUSE ARGUMENT

  • The cosmological (first cause) argument is more important than the ontological argument.

  • St. Thomas Aquinas rejected the ontological argument but made the cosmological argument the intellectual basis of his theism; Roman Catholic orthodoxy often regards it as proving God’s existence with mathematical certainty.

  • The argument has been influential in Protestant thought and accepted in various forms by eminent philosophers like Aristotle, Descartes, Locke, Leibniz.

  • The argument states we require a reason to account for the world, and this ultimate reason must be self-sufficient, requiring no further cause.

  • God is conceived as the only being self-sufficient and his own reason, not requiring a cause beyond himself.

  • The argument appeals to the human tendency to demand reasons for things and opposes the problematic idea of infinite regress.

  • It is plausible to conceive God as a being that necessarily exists and does not need an external cause.

  • The argument assumes the principle of causation, where causes provide reasons for effects; this assumption is more accepted in Roman Catholic philosophy than among most modern philosophers.

  • Doubts arise about whether the causal principle applies to the world as a whole; if applied analogously, the argument weakens.

  • A major difficulty is understanding how anything could be its own reason, implying it must exist necessarily a priori.

  • It is easier to see a priori necessity in logical relations but much harder to see how existence itself could be logically necessary; non-existence presents no contradiction.

  • While not impossible logically, the notion of God’s necessity remains incomprehensible to many.

  • The cosmological argument is invalid as a complete proof but might retain some probability value:

    • The world is more likely rational if theism is true than if it is not.

    • It is more reasonable to suppose the universe is rational rather than irrational.

  • Many modern thinkers reject this, but science presupposes rational coherence beyond experience, logic, and math.

  • Science prefers hypotheses that make the universe more coherent and rational, even if incomplete.

  • Theism does not yet fully rationalize the universe (e.g., how God is uncaused, problem of evil), but it comes closer than other views.

  • Opposing views often treat the world as a brute fact without explanation.

  • Viewing the world as purpose-driven and valuable is closer to rational explanation than denying purpose or value.

  • By the scientific principle of preferring the hypothesis bringing the universe nearest to a coherent rational system, theism is more acceptable.

  • The cosmological argument’s strong point: it remains incredible that the physical universe just happened by chance, even if composed of trillions of electrons.

  • The universe calls out for some further explanation beyond mere physical occurrence.

Membership Required

You must be a member to access this content.

View Membership Levels

Already a member? Log in here

You cannot copy content of this page

error: Content is protected !!
Scroll to Top