Book No. –  19 (Philosophy)

Book Name The Fundamental Questions of Philosophy – A.C. Ewing

What’s Inside the Chapter? (After Subscription)

1. ABSOLUTE v. RELATIVE THEORY

2. BEARING ON PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN PHYSICS

3. THE PROBLEMS OF INFINITY

4. DIFFICULTIES ABOUT MAKING TIME ‘UNREAL’

5. OTHER ARGUMENTS AGAINST THE REALITY OF TIME

6. MYSTICISM AND TIME

7. ALLEGED PRECOGNITION

Note: The first chapter of every book is free.

Access this chapter with any subscription below:

  • Half Yearly Plan (All Subject)
  • Annual Plan (All Subject)
  • Philosophy (Single Subject)
  • CUET PG + Philosophy
  • UGC NET + Philosophy
LANGUAGE

Space and Time

Chapter – 7

Picture of Harshit Sharma
Harshit Sharma

Alumnus (BHU)

Follow
Table of Contents

ABSOLUTE v. RELATIVE THEORY

  • The discussion now turns to space and time themselves, beyond things and events within them.

  • The topic is very difficult and cannot be adequately treated in an elementary philosophy work.

  • The first question is whether space and time exist independently of the things and events they contain.

  • Traditionally, space is seen as a vast receptacle including the entire physical world; a similar idea applies to time, though time’s passing makes metaphor difficult.

  • This traditional view is called the absolute theory of space and time.

  • Language supports this view: we say things are “in space” and “in time”, unlike other properties (e.g., we don’t say all red things are in one big “Red”).

  • The absolute theory is difficult to defend logically.

  • When we try to conceive space apart from physical things or time apart from events, the concepts become vacuous or lose meaning.

  • We can imagine empty space between things, but can we imagine space outside the entire physical universe?

  • There is no empirical evidence for absolute space and time since we only perceive things in space and time, never space or time themselves.

  • The doctrine that space and time cannot act as causes prevents using causal arguments to support absolute theory.

  • Despite difficulties, the absolute theory has been widely accepted by philosophers and ordinary people.

  • One major reason philosophers accepted it was its supposed necessity for classical physics (Newtonian laws of motion).

  • This reason has now disappeared because modern physics, influenced by Einstein’s discoveries, is incompatible with absolute space and time.

  • Philosophers cannot reasonably oppose scientists on this point.

  • It is better to regard space and time as ways of looking at spatial and temporal properties and relations of things and events, not as independent entities.

  • This is the relative theory of space and time (distinct from the scientific theory of Relativity, which includes more complex propositions).

  • Our experience includes spatial properties like size, shape, and distance; geometry makes general statements about these.

  • Talking about a vacuum does not mean space is a positive thing there; it means boundaries have a relation of distance without anything in between.

  • The relative theory rejects absolute points; points are seen as abstract limits approached by division but never reached.

  • The theory also rejects absolute motion.

  • Motion is simply change of position relative to other objects, except where force is involved.

  • For example, if I walk twenty miles, it is equally true that everything else has moved twenty miles relative to me as that I have moved twenty miles relative to everything else.

  • The difference arises only if motion implies force; I feel tired because I have exerted force, but you, though stationary, have also changed your relative position but feel no fatigue.

BEARING ON PHILOSOPHY OF MODERN PHYSICS

  • It is difficult to discuss the philosophical implications of modern physics fully without advanced qualifications in both philosophy and science.

  • An important alleged implication is that time is inseparable from space.

  • Bergson distinguishes between time of physics and time of living experience.

  • The time of physics is measured in terms of space and thus already assimilated to space.

  • The time of psychological life (experienced time) need not share the same properties as physical time.

  • Time may be called the fourth dimension in the sense that:

    • To fix an event’s position completely in space and time, four independent pieces of information are needed.

    • For graphing, time can be treated like a spatial dimension (e.g., plotting depth vs. distance or depth vs. seasonal changes).

  • However, time is not homogeneous with spatial dimensions:

    • Spatial dimensions are interchangeable with no intrinsic difference in their relations (length, breadth, height are arbitrary labels).

    • Time has an intrinsic difference as it represents the relation of before and after.

  • Time is irreversible; unlike space, we cannot move backward in time.

  • Philosophically, it is wrong to assimilate time to space, though scientifically they may be combined in a spatio-temporal system.

  • Two unlike things may be combined in a system because they complement each other, which may be the case for space and time.

  • Caution is needed in applying scientific statements directly to philosophy.

  • Scientific statements (e.g., space is curved, the universe is four-dimensional, physical space is non-Euclidean) may be true only in a “Pickwickian” sense—a sense different from the literal meaning.

  • It may be difficult to identify when expressions are used in a Pickwickian sense and what that sense is.

  • It is safer to conclude that Euclid’s axioms and postulates probably do not apply perfectly to the physical world.

  • This contributes to the modern distrust of the a priori, but it does not undermine the internal a priori necessity of pure geometry.

  • We know a priori that if Euclid’s postulates were true, their conclusions would logically follow.

  • We also know a priori that nothing exists that conforms to the premises but not the conclusions of Euclid.

  • No a priori knowledge, inside or outside geometry, is both affirmative and categorical.

  • A priori knowledge can be hypothetical and practical.

  • By combining a priori hypothetical knowledge with empirical premises, we can derive affirmative categorical conclusions.

  • We lack the empirical premise that the physical world is Euclidean but have the premise that it approximates Euclidean geometry closely except at very small distances or high velocities.

  • Therefore, applied Euclidean geometry remains useful despite Einstein’s discoveries.

Membership Required

You must be a member to access this content.

View Membership Levels

Already a member? Log in here

You cannot copy content of this page

error: Content is protected !!
Scroll to Top