Chapter Info (Click Here)
Book No. – 19 (Philosophy)
Book Name – The Fundamental Questions of Philosophy – A.C. Ewing
What’s Inside the Chapter? (After Subscription)
1. MEANING OF THE DISTINCTION, A PRIORI CHARACTER OF MATHEMATICS
2. THE ‘A PRIORE IN LOGIC
3. OTHER CASES OF THE ‘A PRIORI
4. THE LINGUISTIC THEORY OF THE ‘A PRIORS AND THE DENIAL THAT ‘A PRIORI PROPOSITIONS OR INFERENCES CAN GIVE NEW KNOWLEDGE
5. LANGUAGE AND THOUGHT
6. THE DEFINITION OF MEANING IN TERMS OF VERIFIABILITY AND THE REJECTION OF METAPHYSICS
7. INNATE IDEAS
8. LIMITS OF RATIONALISM
9. INDUCTION
10. INTUITION
11. DISTINCTION BETWEEN KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEE
Note: The first chapter of every book is free.
Access this chapter with any subscription below:
- Half Yearly Plan (All Subject)
- Annual Plan (All Subject)
- Philosophy (Single Subject)
- CUET PG + Philosophy
- UGC NET + Philosophy
The ‘A Priori’ and the Empirical
Chapter – 2

MEANING OF THE DISTINCTION, A PRIORI’ CHARACTER OF MATHEMATICS
In the theory of knowledge, a key distinction is made between two kinds of knowledge: a priori and empirical.
Empirical knowledge is obtained by observation of the external world (sense-perception) and ourselves (introspection).
A priori knowledge is gained by thinking alone, without requiring sensory experience.
Examples of a priori knowledge are primarily found in logic and mathematics.
For instance, to know that 5 + 7 = 12, we do not need to count physical objects; we know it just by thinking.
A crucial difference: a priori knowledge shows that something must be true and explains why it is true, while empirical knowledge only shows that something is true in fact.
Observing a flower is yellow tells us it is yellow but not why it must be yellow; it could have been red.
Mathematical truths like 5 + 7 = 12 are necessarily true, and it is absurd to think otherwise.
It is conceivable that objects might fuse or vanish, reducing the count, but it is inconceivable that 5 + 7 things could be less than 12 simultaneously.
Saying something is inconceivable means a positive insight: it is logically impossible, not just difficult to imagine.
Empirical propositions are contingent: they are true but might have been false.
A priori propositions are necessary: they must be true and cannot be otherwise.
For example, laws of motion might have been different, but arithmetic laws cannot be false for anything countable.
It is conceivable the universe could be a homogeneous fluid without distinct objects, making arithmetic not applicable, but arithmetic must hold for anything that can be numbered.
Although understanding arithmetic initially requires examples, once learned, we do not need examples to grasp or prove new arithmetic truths.
For example, we know 3112 + 2467 = 5579 without ever physically counting that many objects.
Examples serve only to help understand the concept of number, not to prove arithmetic truths.
In geometry, examples are psychologically more needed; people often need drawn figures or mental images to understand proofs.
However, geometric proofs are not based on the actual figures drawn; measurements are not part of Euclid’s proofs.
We can follow proofs even if the illustrative figure is badly drawn or not accurate.
If geometry were empirical, it would be risky to conclude that all triangles share a property based on a single example; it might be an exception.
Recent developments in geometry, such as non-Euclidean geometries, have loosened the connection between geometric proofs and empirical figures.
Some geometries can be developed without relying on actual physical figures.
THE ‘A PRIORI’ IN LOGIC
Another important field of a priori knowledge is logic.
The laws of logic must be known a priori; they cannot be derived from empirical observation.
The purpose of logical argument is to provide conclusions not discovered by observation; if conclusions were already observed, argument would be unnecessary.
Inference works because of a logical connection between premises and conclusion: if the premises are true, the conclusion must be true.
Knowing the premises allows us to assert the conclusion without waiting for experience.
Example story: Mr. X. is revealed as a murderer by inference, not observation — because he was the first penitent to a priest who heard a murder confession.
This type of inference is called a syllogism.
Syllogism example:
Premise 1: The first penitent was a murderer.
Premise 2: Mr. X was the first penitent.
Conclusion: Mr. X was a murderer.
Syllogisms have sometimes been overemphasized, but they are as important as any form of inference.
They allow us to gain information not previously observed or known directly.
Inference depends on the special logical connections between propositions, not on observation.
Logic’s chief function is to study these connections, with the syllogism being only one kind.
A syllogism consists of three propositions: two premises and one conclusion.
Each proposition has a subject and predicate connected by the verb “to be” (the copula).
There are exactly three terms in a syllogism: one is the middle term common to both premises.
The middle term connects the other two terms, which appear together only in the conclusion.
Example:
All men are mortal (middle term: man)
Socrates is a man
Therefore, Socrates is mortal
The middle term “man” links “Socrates” to “mortal,” enabling us to conclude Socrates is mortal even if we never observed his death.