Chapter Info (Click Here)
Book Name – An Introduction to Ethics (William Lillie)
What’s Inside the Chapter? (After Subscription)
1. The Meaning of Law
2. The Moral Law as a Political Law
3. The Moral Law as a Law of Nature
4. The Moral Law as a Law of Reason
5. The Theory of Kant
6. Conclusion
Note: The first chapter of every book is free.
Access this chapter with any subscription below:
- Half Yearly Plan (All Subject)
- Annual Plan (All Subject)
- Sociology (Single Subject)
- CUET PG + Philosophy
- UGC NET + Philosophy
The Standard as Law
Chapter – 8

The Meaning of Law
In ordinary life, we recognize two kinds of laws: political laws and laws of nature.
Political laws:
Made by a sovereign government for all subjects or a certain class.
Subjects may disobey, but disobedience incurs punishment; without punishment, law loses authority.
Vary from country to country and over time; new circumstances (e.g., war) create new laws.
Some deal with morality (e.g., murder forbidden by both political and moral laws).
Laws of nature (scientific laws):
Universal statements of fact describing relations between events (e.g., law of gravitation).
Differ from political laws as statements of fact, not commands; cannot be disobeyed if valid.
Cannot be changed, though applications may vary under different conditions.
Like political laws, they have universal reference: political laws apply to all in a group, scientific laws apply to all objects/events of a kind.
Term “law” may originate from belief they were God’s commands for the universe.
Range of application differs in both law types:
Political: Some apply indiscriminately (e.g., murder laws), others selectively (e.g., income-tax laws).
Scientific:
Universal laws (unconditional, e.g., gravitation)
Hypothetical laws (conditional, e.g., Malthusian population law under certain historical conditions)
Kant: Introduced hypothetical imperative – a law resembling commands more than factual statements.
Example: Builder obeys rules depending on materials and object (permanent cathedral vs. temporary shelter).
Can be disobeyed, but then the intended outcome is not achieved.
Requires consideration of facts of nature (e.g., material properties).
Essentially a scientific law of limited kind: statement of means to achieve a certain end or cause producing an effect.
Appearance of command arises from someone’s wish or order (builder or customer).
Such laws are subordinate imperatives, obeyed derivatively because another command exists.
Accepting the obligation to build entails accepting obligations dictated by laws of architecture.
In economics, we find examples of three kinds of laws: scientific, political, and hypothetical/normative.
Economics contains scientific laws, mostly hypothetical, holding only under certain conditions, e.g., law of supply and demand—price rises with increased demand or decreased supply.
Economics also involves political laws, such as government regulations controlling prices and rents.
It provides rules, or subordinate imperatives, e.g., guidelines to increase national wealth.
Some writers call these hypothetical imperatives or normative laws, but others reserve normative law for rules holding universally for all people.
Dominant imperatives are universal; subordinate imperatives are instrumental to them.
Some argue no universal imperatives exist; people follow subordinate imperatives only to achieve desired outcomes or due to compulsion.
Ethics and religion are the most likely sources of categorical imperatives or universal rules.
Attempts to equate aesthetics or logic with ethics/religion are questionable; obligations in these areas are often moral, not aesthetic/logical.
Laws of religion are harder to classify; often seen as political commands of God rather than moral laws.
Kant distinguished three kinds of normative laws (imperatives):
Hypothetical imperative: Holds for specific groups pursuing particular ends, e.g., laws of architecture.
Assertorial imperative: Universally applicable conditional rules based on ends all naturally seek, e.g., happiness; many moral laws are seen as assertorial.
Categorical imperative: Holds unconditionally and universally; the moral law is the only example.
Moral laws do not depend on outcomes, rejecting teleological ethics.
Kant: “Nothing is good without qualification except a good will”; other goodness is conditional and hypothetical.
Three remarks on Kant’s categorical imperative:
The term imperative implies a command, possibly divine; it emphasizes obligatoriness, like legal authority.
Challenge: understanding how a good will acts or applies the categorical imperative to specific decisions.
Moral law is obligatory only for rational beings, so it is conditional on being apprehended by a rational mind; Kant noted it must be self-imposed.